WEST VIRGINIA
STATE BOARD OF EDUCATION ET AL. v. BARNETTE ET AL.
No. 591
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
319 U.S. 624; 63 S. Ct. 1178; 1943 U.S. LEXIS 490; 87 L.
Ed. 1628; 147 A.L.R. 674
March 11, 1943, Argued
June 14, 1943, Decided
PRIOR HISTORY: APPEAL FROM THE DISTRICT COURT OF THE UNITED
STATES FOR THE SOUTHERN DISTRICT OF WEST VIRGINIA.
OPINIONBY: [***3] JACKSON
OPINION: [*625] [**1179] MR. JUSTICE
JACKSON delivered the opinion of the Court.
Following the decision by this Court on June 3, 1940, in Minersville School
District v. Gobitis, 310 U.S. 586, the West Virginia legislature
amended its statutes to require all schools therein to conduct courses of
instruction in history, civics, and in the Constitutions of the United States
and of the State "for the purpose of teaching, fostering and perpetuating
the ideals, principles and spirit of Americanism, and increasing the knowledge
of the organization and machinery of the government." Appellant
[*626] Board of Education was directed, with advice of the State
Superintendent of Schools, to "prescribe the courses of study covering
these subjects" for public schools. The Act made it the duty of private,
parochial and denominational schools to prescribe courses of study
"similar to those required for the public schools." n1
- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -Footnotes- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -
n1 § 1734, West Virginia Code (1941 Supp.):
"In all public, private, parochial and denominational schools located
within this state there shall be given regular courses of instruction in
history of the United States, in civics, and in the constitutions of the United
States and of the State of West Virginia, for the purpose of teaching,
fostering and perpetuating the ideals, principles and spirit of Americanism,
and increasing the knowledge of the organization and machinery of the
government of the United States and of the state of West Virginia. The state
board of education shall, with the advice of the state superintendent of
schools, prescribe the courses of study covering these subjects for the public
elementary and grammar schools, public high schools and state normal schools.
It shall be the duty of the officials or boards having authority over the
respective private, parochial and denominational schools to prescribe courses
of study for the schools under their control and supervision similar to those
required for the public schools."
- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -End Footnotes- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -
[***4]
The Board of Education on January 9, 1942, adopted a resolution containing
recitals taken largely from the Court's Gobitis opinion and ordering
that the salute to the flag become "a regular part of the program of
activities in the public schools," that all teachers and pupils
"shall be required to participate in the salute honoring the Nation
represented by the Flag; provided, however, that refusal to salute the Flag be
regarded as an act of insubordination, and shall be dealt with
accordingly." n2
- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -Footnotes- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -
n2 The text is as follows:
"WHEREAS, The West Virginia State Board of Education holds in highest
regard those rights and privileges guaranteed by the Bill of Rights in the
Constitution of the United States of America and in the Constitution of West
Virginia, specifically, the first amendment to the Constitution of the United
States as restated in the fourteenth amendment to the same document and in the
guarantee of religious freedom in Article III of the Constitution of this
State, and
"WHEREAS, The West Virginia State Board of Education honors the broad
principle that one's convictions about the ultimate mystery of the universe and
man's relation to it is placed beyond the reach of law; that the propagation of
belief is protected whether in church or chapel, mosque or synagogue,
tabernacle or meeting house; that the Constitutions of the United States and of
the State of West Virginia assure generous immunity to the individual from
imposition of penalty for offending, in the course of his own religious
activities, the religious views of others, be they a minority or those who are
dominant in the government, but
"WHEREAS, The West Virginia State Board of Education recognizes that the
manifold character of man's relations may bring his conception of religious
duty into conflict with the secular interests of his fellowman; that
conscientious scruples have not in the course of the long struggle for
religious toleration relieved the individual from obedience to the general law
not aimed at the promotion or restriction of the religious beliefs; that the
mere possession of convictions which contradict the relevant concerns of
political society does not relieve the citizen from the discharge of political
responsibility, and
"WHEREAS, The West Virginia State Board of Education holds that national
unity is the basis of national security; that the flag of our Nation is the
symbol of our National Unity transcending all internal differences, however
large within the framework of the Constitution; that the Flag is the symbol of
the Nation's power; that emblem of freedom in its truest, best sense; that it
signifies government resting on the consent of the governed, liberty regulated
by law, protection of the weak against the strong, security against the
exercise of arbitrary power, and absolute safety for free institutions against
foreign aggression, and
"WHEREAS, The West Virginia State Board of Education maintains that the
public schools, established by the legislature of the State of West Virginia
under the authority of the Constitution of the State of West Virginia and
supported by taxes imposed by legally constituted measures, are dealing with
the formative period in the development in citizenship that the Flag is an
allowable portion of the program of schools thus publicly supported.
"Therefore, be it RESOLVED, That the West Virginia Board of Education does
hereby recognize and order that the commonly accepted salute to the Flag of the
United States -- the right hand is placed upon the breast and the following
pledge repeated in unison: 'I pledge allegiance to the Flag of the United States
of America and to the Republic for which it stands; one Nation, indivisible,
with liberty and justice for all' -- now becomes a regular part of the program
of activities in the public schools, supported in whole or in part by public
funds, and that all teachers as defined by law in West Virginia and pupils in
such schools shall be required to participate in the salute, honoring the
Nation represented by the Flag; provided, however, that refusal to salute the
Flag be regarded as an act of insubordination, and shall be dealt with
accordingly."
- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -End Footnotes- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -
[***5]
[*627] The resolution originally required the "
[**1180] commonly accepted salute to the Flag" which it
defined. Objections to the salute as "being too much like Hitler's"
were raised by the Parent and Teachers Association, the Boy and Girl
[*628] Scouts, the Red Cross, and the Federation of Women's Clubs.
n3 Some modification appears to have been made in deference to these
objections, but no concession was made to Jehovah's Witnesses. n4 What is now
required is the "stiff-arm" salute, the saluter to keep the right
hand raised with palm turned up [**1181] while the following is
repeated: "I pledge allegiance to the Flag of the United States of
[*629] America and to the Republic for which it stands; one Nation,
indivisible, with liberty and justice for all."
- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -Footnotes- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -
n3 The National Headquarters of the United States Flag Association takes the
position that the extension of the right arm in this salute to the flag is not
the Nazi-Fascist salute, "although quite similar to it. In the Pledge to
the Flag the right arm is extended and raised, palm UPWARD, whereas the Nazis
extend the arm practically straight to the front (the finger tips
being about even with the eyes), palm DOWNWARD, and the Fascists do
the same except they raise the arm slightly higher." James A. Moss, The
Flag of the United States: Its History and Symbolism (1914) 108.
[***6]
n4 They have offered in lieu of participating in the flag salute ceremony
"periodically and publicly" to give the following pledge:
"I have pledged my unqualified allegiance and devotion to Jehovah, the
Almighty God, and to His Kingdom, for which Jesus commands all Christians to
pray.
"I respect the flag of the United States and acknowledge it as a symbol of
freedom and justice to all.
"I pledge allegiance and obedience to all the laws of the United States
that are consistent with God's law, as set forth in the Bible."
- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -End Footnotes- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -
Failure to conform is "insubordination" dealt with by expulsion.
Readmission is denied by statute until compliance. Meanwhile the expelled child
is "unlawfully absent" n5 and may be proceeded against as a
delinquent. n6 His parents or guardians are liable to prosecution, n7 and if
convicted are subject to fine not exceeding $ 50 and jail term not exceeding
thirty days. n8
- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -Footnotes- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -
n5 § 1851 (1), West Virginia Code (1941 Supp.):
"If a child be dismissed, suspended, or expelled from school because of
refusal of such child to meet the legal and lawful requirements of the school
and the established regulations of the county and/or state board of education,
further admission of the child to school shall be refused until such
requirements and regulations be complied with. Any such child shall be treated
as being unlawfully absent from school during the time he refuses to comply
with such requirements and regulations, and any person having legal or actual
control of such child shall be liable to prosecution under the provisions of this
article for the absence of such child from school." [***7]
n6 § 4904 (4), West Virginia Code (1941 Supp.).
n7 See Note 5, supra.
n8 §§ 1847, 1851, West Virginia Code (1941 Supp.).
- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -End Footnotes- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -
Appellees, citizens of the United States and of West Virginia, brought suit in
the United States District Court for themselves and others similarly situated
asking its injunction to restrain enforcement of these laws and regulations against
Jehovah's Witnesses. The Witnesses are an unincorporated body teaching that the
obligation imposed by law of God is superior to that of laws enacted by
temporal government. Their religious beliefs include a literal version of
Exodus, Chapter 20, verses 4 and 5, which says: "Thou shalt not make unto
thee any graven image, or any likeness of anything that is in heaven above, or
that is in the earth beneath, or that is in the water under the earth; thou
shalt not bow down thyself to them nor serve them." They consider that the
flag is an "image" within this command. For this reason they refuse
to salute it.
[*630] Children of this faith have been expelled from school and
are threatened with exclusion for no other cause. [***8] Officials
threaten to send them to reformatories maintained for criminally inclined
juveniles. Parents of such children have been prosecuted and are threatened
with prosecutions for causing delinquency.
The Board of Education moved to dismiss the complaint setting forth these facts
and alleging that the law and regulations are an unconstitutional denial of
religious freedom, and of freedom of speech, and are invalid under the
"due process" and "equal protection" clauses of the
Fourteenth Amendment to the Federal Constitution. The cause was submitted on
the pleadings to a District Court of three judges. It restrained enforcement as
to the plaintiffs and those of that class. The Board of Education brought the
case here by direct appeal. n9
- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -Footnotes- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -
n9 § 266 of the Judicial Code, 28 U. S. C. § 380.
- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -End Footnotes- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -
[1]
This case calls upon us to reconsider a precedent decision, as the Court
throughout its history often has been required to do. n10 Before turning to the
Gobitis case, however, it is desirable to notice certain
characteristics [***9] by which this controversy is distinguished.
- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -Footnotes- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -
n10 See authorities cited in Helvering v. Griffiths, 318 U.S.
371, 401, note 52.
- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -End Footnotes- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -
The freedom asserted by these appellees does not bring them into collision with
rights asserted by any other individual. It is such conflicts which most
frequently require intervention of the State to determine where the rights of
one end and those of another begin. But the refusal of these persons to
participate in the ceremony does not interfere with or deny rights of others to
do so. Nor is there any question in this case that their behavior is peaceable
and orderly. The sole conflict is between authority and rights of the
individual. The State asserts power to condition access to public education on
making a prescribed sign and profession and at the same time to coerce
[*631] attendance by punishing both parent and child. The latter
stand on a right [**1182] of self-determination in matters that
touch individual opinion and personal attitude.
As the present CHIEF JUSTICE said [***10] in dissent in the Gobitis
case, the State may "require teaching by instruction and study of all in
our history and in the structure and organization of our government, including
the guaranties of civil liberty, which tend to inspire patriotism and love of
country." 310 U.S. at 604. Here, however, we are dealing with a compulsion
of students to declare a belief. They are not merely made acquainted with the flag
salute so that they may be informed as to what it is or even what it means. The
issue here is whether this slow and easily neglected n11 route to aroused
loyalties constitutionally may be short-cut by substituting a compulsory salute
and slogan. n12 This issue is not prejudiced by [*632] the Court's
previous holding that where a State, without compelling attendance, extends
college facilities to pupils who voluntarily enroll, it may prescribe military
training as part of the course without offense to the Constitution. It was held
that those who take advantage of its opportunities may not on ground of
conscience refuse compliance with such conditions. Hamilton v. Regents,
293 U.S. 245. In the present case attendance is not optional. That case is also
to be [***11] distinguished from the present one because,
independently of college privileges or requirements, the State has power to
raise militia and impose the duties of service therein upon its citizens.
- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -Footnotes- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -
n11 See the nation-wide survey of the study of American history conducted by
the New York Times, the results of which are published in the issue of June 21,
1942, and are there summarized on p. 1, col. 1, as follows:
"82 per cent of the institutions of higher learning in the United States
do not require the study of United States history for the undergraduate degree.
Eighteen per cent of the colleges and universities require such history courses
before a degree is awarded. It was found that many students complete their four
years in college without taking any history courses dealing with this country.
"Seventy-two per cent of the colleges and universities do not require
United States history for admission, while 28 per cent require it. As a result,
the survey revealed, many students go through high school, college and then to
the professional or graduate institution without having explored courses in the
history of their country.
"Less than 10 per cent of the total undergraduate body was enrolled in
United States history classes during the Spring semester just ended. Only 8 per
cent of the freshman class took courses in United States history, although 30
per cent was enrolled in European or world history courses." [***12]
n12 The Resolution of the Board of Education did not adopt the flag salute
because it was claimed to have educational value. It seems to have been
concerned with promotion of national unity (see footnote 2), which
justification is considered later in this opinion. No information as to its
educational aspect is called to our attention except Olander, Children's
Knowledge of the Flag Salute, 35 Journal of Educational Research 300, 305,
which sets forth a study of the ability of a large and representative number of
children to remember and state the meaning of the flag salute which they
recited each day in school. His conclusion was that it revealed "a rather
pathetic picture of our attempts to teach children not only the words but the
meaning of our Flag Salute."
- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -End Footnotes- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -
There is no doubt that, in connection with the pledges, the flag salute is a
form of utterance. Symbolism is a primitive but effective way of communicating
ideas. The use of an emblem or flag to symbolize some system, idea,
institution, or personality, is a short cut from mind to mind. Causes and
nations, political parties, lodges [***13] and ecclesiastical
groups seek to knit the loyalty of their followings to a flag or banner, a
color or design. The State announces rank, function, and authority through
crowns and maces, uniforms and black robes; the church speaks through the
Cross, the Crucifix, the altar and shrine, and clerical raiment. Symbols of
State often convey political ideas just as religious symbols come to convey
theological ones. Associated with many of these symbols are appropriate
gestures of acceptance or respect: a salute, a bowed or bared head, a bended
knee. A person gets from a [*633] symbol the meaning he puts into
it, and [**1183] what is one man's comfort and inspiration is
another's jest and scorn.
Over a decade ago Chief Justice Hughes led this Court in holding that the
display of a red flag as a symbol of opposition by peaceful and legal means to
organized government was protected by the free speech guaranties of the
Constitution. Stromberg v. California, 283 U.S. 359. Here it
is the State that employs a flag as a symbol of adherence to government as
presently organized. It requires the individual to communicate by word and sign
his acceptance of the political ideas it thus bespeaks. [***14]
Objection to this form of communication when coerced is an old one, well known
to the framers of the Bill of Rights. n13
- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -Footnotes- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -
n13 Early Christians were frequently persecuted for their refusal to
participate in ceremonies before the statute of the emperor or other symbol of
imperial authority. The story of William Tell's sentence to shoot an apple off
his son's head for refusal to salute a bailiff's hat is an ancient one. 21
Encyclopedia Britannica (14th ed.) 911-912. The Quakers, William Penn included,
suffered punishment rather than uncover their heads in deference to any civil
authority. Braithwaite, The Beginnings of Quakerism (1912) 200, 229-230,
232-233, 447, 451; Fox, Quakers Courageous (1941) 113.
- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -End Footnotes- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -
It is also to be noted that the compulsory flag salute and pledge requires
affirmation of a belief and an attitude of mind. It is not clear whether the
regulation contemplates that pupils forego any contrary convictions of their
own and become unwilling converts to the prescribed ceremony or whether it will
be acceptable [***15] if they simulate assent by words without
belief and by a gesture barren of meaning. It is now a commonplace that
censorship or suppression of expression of opinion is tolerated by our
Constitution only when the expression presents a clear and present danger of
action of a kind the State is empowered to prevent and punish. It would seem
that involuntary affirmation could be commanded only on even more immediate and
urgent grounds than silence. But here the power of compulsion
[*634] is invoked without any allegation that remaining passive
during a flag salute ritual creates a clear and present danger that would
justify an effort even to muffle expression. To sustain the compulsory flag
salute we are required to say that a Bill of Rights which guards the
individual's right to speak his own mind, left it open to public authorities to
compel him to utter what is not in his mind.
Whether the First Amendment to the Constitution will permit officials to order
observance of ritual of this nature does not depend upon whether as a voluntary
exercise we would think it to be good, bad or merely innocuous. Any credo of
nationalism is likely to include what some disapprove or to omit
[***16] what others think essential, and to give off different
overtones as it takes on different accents or interpretations. n14 If official
power exists to coerce acceptance of any patriotic creed, what it shall contain
cannot be decided by courts, but must be largely discretionary with the ordaining
authority, whose power to prescribe would no doubt include power to amend.
Hence validity of the asserted power to force an American citizen publicly to
profess any statement of belief or to engage in any ceremony of assent to one,
presents questions of power that must be considered independently of any idea
we may have as to the utility of the ceremony in question.
- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -Footnotes- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -
n14 For example: Use of "Republic," if rendered to distinguish our
government from a "democracy," or the words "one Nation,"
if intended to distinguish it from a "federation," open up old and
bitter controversies in our political history; "liberty and justice for
all," if it must be accepted as descriptive of the present order rather
than an ideal, might to some seem an overstatement.
- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -End Footnotes- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -
[***17]
Nor does the issue as we see it turn on one's possession of particular religious
views or the sincerity with which they are held. While religion supplies
appellees' motive for enduring the discomforts of making the issue in this
case, many citizens who do not share these religious views [*635]
hold such a compulsory rite to infringe constitutional liberty of the
individual. n15 It is not necessary to inquire whether non-conformist beliefs
will exempt [**1184] from the duty to salute unless we first find
power to make the salute a legal duty.
- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -Footnotes- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -
n15 Cushman, Constitutional Law in 1939-40, 35 American Political Science
Review 250, 271, observes: "All of the eloquence by which the majority
extol the ceremony of flag saluting as a free expression of patriotism turns
sour when used to describe the brutal compulsion which requires a sensitive and
conscientious child to stultify himself in public." For further criticism
of the opinion in the Gobitis case by persons who do not share the
faith of the Witnesses see: Powell, Conscience and the Constitution, in
Democracy and National Unity (University of Chicago Press, 1941) 1; Wilkinson,
Some Aspects of the Constitutional Guarantees of Civil Liberty, 11 Fordham Law
Review 50; Fennell, The "Reconstructed Court" and Religious Freedom:
The Gobitis Case in Retrospect, 19 New York University Law Quarterly Review 31;
Green, Liberty under the Fourteenth Amendment, 27 Washington University Law
Quarterly 497; 9 International Juridical Association Bulletin 1; 39 Michigan Law
Review 149; 15 St. John's Law Review 95.
- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -End Footnotes- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -
[***18]
The Gobitis decision, however, assumed, as did the argument
in that case and in this, that power exists in the State to impose the flag
salute discipline upon school children in general. The Court only examined and
rejected a claim based on religious beliefs of immunity from an unquestioned
general rule. n16 The question which underlies the [*636] flag salute
controversy is whether such a ceremony so touching matters of opinion and
political attitude may be imposed upon the individual by official authority
under powers committed to any political organization under our Constitution. We
examine rather than assume existence of this power and, against this broader
definition of issues in this case, reexamine specific grounds assigned for the Gobitis
decision.
- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -Footnotes- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -
n16 The opinion says "That the flag-salute is an allowable portion of a
school program for those who do not invoke conscientious scruples is surely
not debatable. But for us to insist that, though the ceremony may be
required, exceptional immunity must be given to dissidents, is to maintain
that there is no basis for a legislative judgment that such an exemption might
introduce elements of difficulty into the school discipline, might cast doubts
in the minds of the other children which would themselves weaken the effect of
the exercise." (Italics ours.) 310 U.S. at 599-600. And elsewhere the
question under consideration was stated, "When does the constitutional
guarantee compel exemption from doing what society thinks necessary
for the promotion of some great common end, or from a penalty for conduct which
appears dangerous to the general good?" (Italics ours.) Id. at
593. And again, ". . . whether school children, like the Gobitis children,
must be excused from conduct required of all the other children in the
promotion of national cohesion. . . ." (Italics ours.) Id. at
595.
- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -End Footnotes- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -
[***19]
1. It was said that the flag-salute controversy confronted the Court with
"the problem which Lincoln cast in memorable dilemma: 'Must a government
of necessity be too strong for the liberties of its people, or too weak
to maintain its own existence?'" and that the answer must be in favor of
strength. Minersville School District v. Gobitis, supra, at
596.
We think these issues may be examined free of pressure or restraint growing out
of such considerations.
It may be doubted whether Mr. Lincoln would have thought that the strength of
government to maintain itself would be impressively vindicated by our
confirming power of the State to expel a handful of children from school. Such
oversimplification, so handy in political debate, often lacks the precision
necessary to postulates of judicial reasoning. If validly applied to this
problem, the utterance cited would resolve every issue of power in favor of
those in authority and would require us to override every liberty thought to
weaken or delay execution of their policies.
Government of limited power need not be anemic government. Assurance that
rights are secure tends to diminish fear and jealousy of strong government,
[***20] and by [**1185] making us feel safe to live
under it makes for its better support. Without promise of a limiting Bill of
Rights it is [*637] doubtful if our Constitution could have
mustered enough strength to enable its ratification. To enforce those rights
today is not to choose weak government over strong government. It is only to
adhere as a means of strength to individual freedom of mind in preference to
officially disciplined uniformity for which history indicates a disappointing
and disastrous end.
The subject now before us exemplifies this principle. Free public education, if
faithful to the ideal of secular instruction and political neutrality, will not
be partisan or enemy of any class, creed, party, or faction. If it is to impose
any ideological discipline, however, each party or denomination must seek to
control, or failing that, to weaken the influence of the educational system.
Observance of the limitations of the Constitution will not weaken government in
the field appropriate for its exercise.
2. It was also considered in the Gobitis case that functions of
educational officers in States, counties and school districts were such that to
interfere with their authority [***21] "would in effect make
us the school board for the country." Id. at 598.
The Fourteenth Amendment, as now applied to the States, protects the citizen
against the State itself and all of its creatures -- Boards of Education not
excepted. These have, of course, important, delicate, and highly discretionary
functions, but none that they may not perform within the limits of the Bill of
Rights. That they are educating the young for citizenship is reason for
scrupulous protection of Constitutional freedoms of the individual, if we are
not to strangle the free mind at its source and teach youth to discount
important principles of our government as mere platitudes.
Such Boards are numerous and their territorial jurisdiction often small. But
small and local authority may feel less sense of responsibility to the
Constitution, and agencies of publicity may be less vigilant in calling it to
account. [*638] The action of Congress in making flag observance
voluntary n17 and respecting the conscience of the objector in a matter so
vital as raising the Army n18 contrasts sharply with these local regulations in
matters relatively trivial to the welfare of the nation. There are village
[***22] tyrants as well as village Hampdens, but none who acts
under color of law is beyond reach of the Constitution.
- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -Footnotes- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -
n17 Section 7 of House Joint Resolution 359, approved December 22, 1942, 56
Stat. 1074, 36 U. S. C. (1942 Supp.) § 172, prescribes no penalties for
nonconformity but provides:
"That the pledge of allegiance to the flag, 'I pledge allegiance to the
flag of the United States of America and to the Republic for which it stands,
one Nation indivisible, with liberty and justice for all,' be rendered by
standing with the right hand over the heart. However, civilians will always
show full respect to the flag when the pledge is given by merely standing at
attention, men removing the headdress . . ."
n18 § 5 (a) of the Selective Training and Service Act of 1940, 50 U. S. C.
(App.) § 307 (g).
- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -End Footnotes- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -
3. The Gobitis opinion reasoned that this is a field "where
courts possess no marked and certainly no controlling competence," that it
is committed to the legislatures as well as the courts to guard cherished
liberties [***23] and that it is constitutionally appropriate to
"fight out the wise use of legislative authority in the forum of public
opinion and before legislative assemblies rather than to transfer such a
contest to the judicial arena," since all the "effective means of
inducing political changes are left free." Id. at 597-598, 600.
The very purpose of a Bill of Rights was to withdraw certain subjects from the
vicissitudes of political controversy, to place them beyond the reach of
majorities and officials and to establish them as legal principles to be
applied by the courts. One's right to life, liberty, and property, to free
speech, a free press, freedom of worship and assembly, and other fundamental
rights may not be submitted [**1186] to vote; they depend on the
outcome of no elections.
[*639]
[2]
In weighing arguments of the parties it is important to distinguish between the
due process clause of the Fourteenth Amendment as an instrument for
transmitting the principles of the First Amendment and those cases in which it
is applied for its own sake. The test of legislation which collides with the
Fourteenth Amendment, because it also collides with the principles of the
First, is much more definite [***24] than the test when only the
Fourteenth is involved. Much of the vagueness of the due process clause
disappears when the specific prohibitions of the First become its standard. The
right of a State to regulate, for example, a public utility may well include,
so far as the due process test is concerned, power to impose all of the
restrictions which a legislature may have a "rational basis" for
adopting. But freedoms of speech and of press, of assembly, and of worship may
not be infringed on such slender grounds. They are susceptible of restriction
only to prevent grave and immediate danger to interests which the State may
lawfully protect. It is important to note that while it is the Fourteenth
Amendment which bears directly upon the State it is the more specific limiting
principles of the First Amendment that finally govern this case.
Nor does our duty to apply the Bill of Rights to assertions of official
authority depend upon our possession of marked competence in the field where
the invasion of rights occurs. True, the task of translating the majestic
generalities of the Bill of Rights, conceived as part of the pattern of liberal
government in the eighteenth century, into [***25] concrete restraints
on officials dealing with the problems of the twentieth century, is one to
disturb self-confidence. These principles grew in soil which also produced a
philosophy that the individual was the center of society, that his liberty was
attainable through mere absence of governmental restraints, and that government
should be entrusted with few controls and only the mildest supervision
[*640] over men's affairs. We must transplant these rights to a
soil in which the laissez-faire concept or principle of non-interference
has withered at least as to economic affairs, and social advancements are
increasingly sought through closer integration of society and through expanded
and strengthened governmental controls. These changed conditions often deprive
precedents of reliability and cast us more than we would choose upon our own
judgment. But we act in these matters not by authority of our competence but by
force of our commissions. We cannot, because of modest estimates of our
competence in such specialties as public education, withhold the judgment that
history authenticates as the function of this Court when liberty is infringed.
4. Lastly, and this is the [***26] very heart of the Gobitis
opinion, it reasons that "National unity is the basis of national
security," that the authorities have "the right to select appropriate
means for its attainment," and hence reaches the conclusion that such
compulsory measures toward "national unity" are constitutional. Id.
at 595. Upon the verity of this assumption depends our answer in this case.
National unity as an end which officials may foster by persuasion and example
is not in question. The problem is whether under our Constitution compulsion as
here employed is a permissible means for its achievement.
Struggles to coerce uniformity of sentiment in support of some end thought
essential to their time and country have been waged by many good as well as by
evil men. Nationalism is a relatively recent phenomenon but at other times and
places the ends have been racial or territorial security, support of a dynasty
or regime, and particular plans for saving souls. As first and moderate methods
to attain unity have failed, those bent on its accomplishment must resort to an
ever-increasing severity. [*641] As governmental pressure toward
unity becomes greater, so strife becomes more bitter [***27] as to
whose unity it shall be. Probably no deeper division of our people could
proceed from any provocation than from finding it necessary to choose what
doctrine and whose program public educational officials shall compel youth to
unite in embracing. Ultimate futility of such attempts to compel coherence is
the lesson [**1187] of every such effort from the Roman drive to
stamp out Christianity as a disturber of its pagan unity, the Inquisition, as a
means to religious and dynastic unity, the Siberian exiles as a means to
Russian unity, down to the fast failing efforts of our present totalitarian
enemies. Those who begin coercive elimination of dissent soon find themselves
exterminating dissenters. Compulsory unification of opinion achieves only the
unanimity of the graveyard.
It seems trite but necessary to say that the First Amendment to our
Constitution was designed to avoid these ends by avoiding these beginnings.
There is no mysticism in the American concept of the State or of the nature or
origin of its authority. We set up government by consent of the governed, and
the Bill of Rights denies those in power any legal opportunity to coerce that
consent. Authority here is to be [***28] controlled by public
opinion, not public opinion by authority.
The case is made difficult not because the principles of its decision are
obscure but because the flag involved is our own. Nevertheless, we apply the
limitations of the Constitution with no fear that freedom to be intellectually
and spiritually diverse or even contrary will disintegrate the social
organization. To believe that patriotism will not flourish if patriotic
ceremonies are voluntary and spontaneous instead of a compulsory routine is to
make an unflattering estimate of the appeal of our institutions to free minds.
We can have intellectual individualism [*642] and the rich cultural
diversities that we owe to exceptional minds only at the price of occasional
eccentricity and abnormal attitudes. When they are so harmless to others or to
the State as those we deal with here, the price is not too great. But freedom
to differ is not limited to things that do not matter much. That would be a
mere shadow of freedom. The test of its substance is the right to differ as to
things that touch the heart of the existing order.
If there is any fixed star in our constitutional constellation, it is that no
official, [***29] high or petty, can prescribe what shall be
orthodox in politics, nationalism, religion, or other matters of opinion or
force citizens to confess by word or act their faith therein. If there are any
circumstances which permit an exception, they do not now occur to us. n19
- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -Footnotes- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -
n19 The Nation may raise armies and compel citizens to give military service. Selective
Draft Law Cases, 245 U.S. 366. It follows, of course, that those subject
to military discipline are under many duties and may not claim many freedoms
that we hold inviolable as to those in civilian life.
- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -End Footnotes- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -
We think the action of the local authorities in compelling the flag salute and
pledge transcends constitutional limitations on their power and invades the
sphere of intellect and spirit which it is the purpose of the First Amendment
to our Constitution to reserve from all official control.
[3]
The decision of this Court in Minersville School District v. Gobitis
and the holdings of those few per curiam decisions which preceded and
foreshadowed it [***30] are overruled, and the judgment enjoining
enforcement of the West Virginia Regulation is
Affirmed.
MR. JUSTICE ROBERTS and MR. JUSTICE REED adhere to the views expressed by the
Court in Minersville School [*643] District v. Gobitis,
310 U.S. 586, and are of the opinion that the judgment below should be
reversed.
CONCURBY: BLACK; DOUGLAS; MURPHY
CONCUR: MR. JUSTICE BLACK and MR. JUSTICE DOUGLAS, concurring:
We are substantially in agreement with the opinion just read, but since we
originally joined with the Court in the Gobitis case, it is
appropriate that we make a brief statement of reasons for our change of view.
Reluctance to make the Federal Constitution a rigid bar against state
regulation of conduct thought inimical to the public welfare was the
controlling influence which moved us to consent to the Gobitis
decision. Long reflection convinced us that although the principle is sound,
its application [**1188] in the particular case was wrong. Jones
v. Opelika, 316 U.S. 584, 623. We believe that the statute before us
fails to accord full scope to the freedom of religion secured to the appellees
by the First and Fourteenth Amendments.
The statute requires the appellees [***31] to participate in a
ceremony aimed at inculcating respect for the flag and for this country. The
Jehovah's Witnesses, without any desire to show disrespect for either the flag
or the country, interpret the Bible as commanding, at the risk of God's
displeasure, that they not go through the form of a pledge of allegiance to any
flag. The devoutness of their belief is evidenced by their willingness to
suffer persecution and punishment, rather than make the pledge.
No well-ordered society can leave to the individuals an absolute right to make
final decisions, unassailable by the State, as to everything they will or will
not do. The First Amendment does not go so far. Religious faiths, honestly
held, do not free individuals from responsibility to conduct themselves
obediently to laws which are either imperatively necessary to protect society
as a whole from grave [*644] and pressingly imminent dangers or
which, without any general prohibition, merely regulate time, place or manner
of religious activity. Decision as to the constitutionality of particular laws
which strike at the substance of religious tenets and practices must be made by
this Court. The duty is a solemn one, [***32] and in meeting it we
cannot say that a failure, because of religious scruples, to assume a
particular physical position and to repeat the words of a patriotic formula
creates a grave danger to the nation. Such a statutory exaction is a form of
test oath, and the test oath has always been abhorrent in the United States.
Words uttered under coercion are proof of loyalty to nothing but self-interest.
Love of country must spring from willing hearts and free minds, inspired by a
fair administration of wise laws enacted by the people's elected representatives
within the bounds of express constitutional prohibitions. These laws must, to
be consistent with the First Amendment, permit the widest toleration of
conflicting viewpoints consistent with a society of free men.
Neither our domestic tranquillity in peace nor our martial effort in war depend
on compelling little children to participate in a ceremony which ends in
nothing for them but a fear of spiritual condemnation. If, as we think, their
fears are groundless, time and reason are the proper antidotes for their
errors. The ceremonial, when enforced against conscientious objectors, more
likely to defeat than to serve its high [***33] purpose, is a handy
implement for disguised religious persecution. As such, it is inconsistent with
our Constitution's plan and purpose.
MR. JUSTICE MURPHY, concurring:
I agree with the opinion of the Court and join in it.
The complaint challenges an order of the State Board of Education which
requires teachers and pupils to participate in the prescribed salute to the
flag. For refusal to conform with the requirement, the State law prescribes
expulsion. [*645] The offender is required by law to be treated as
unlawfully absent from school and the parent or guardian is made liable to
prosecution and punishment for such absence. Thus not only is the privilege of
public education conditioned on compliance with the requirement, but
noncompliance is virtually made unlawful. In effect compliance is compulsory
and not optional. It is the claim of appellees that the regulation is invalid
as a restriction on religious freedom and freedom of speech, secured to them
against State infringement by the First and Fourteenth Amendments to the
Constitution of the United States.
A reluctance to interfere with considered state action, the fact that the end
sought is a desirable one, the [***34] emotion aroused by the flag
as a symbol for which we have fought and are now fighting again, -- all of
these are understandable. But there is before us the right of freedom to
believe, freedom to worship one's Maker according to the dictates of one's
conscience, a right which the Constitution specifically shelters. Reflection
has convinced me that as a judge I have no loftier duty or responsibility than
to uphold that spiritual freedom to its farthest reaches.
The right of freedom of thought and of religion as guaranteed by the
Constitution [**1189] against State action includes both the right
to speak freely and the right to refrain from speaking at all, except insofar
as essential operations of government may require it for the preservation of an
orderly society, -- as in the case of compulsion to give evidence in court.
Without wishing to disparage the purposes and intentions of those who hope to
inculcate sentiments of loyalty and patriotism by requiring a declaration of
allegiance as a feature of public education, or unduly belittle the benefits
that may accrue therefrom, I am impelled to conclude that such a requirement is
not essential to the maintenance of effective government [***35]
and orderly society. To many it is deeply distasteful to join in a public
chorus of affirmation of private belief. By some, including [*646]
the members of this sect, it is apparently regarded as incompatible with a
primary religious obligation and therefore a restriction on religious freedom.
Official compulsion to affirm what is contrary to one's religious beliefs is
the antithesis of freedom of worship which, it is well to recall, was achieved
in this country only after what Jefferson characterized as the "severest
contests in which I have ever been engaged." n1
- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -Footnotes- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -
n1 See Jefferson, Autobiography, vol. 1, pp. 53-59.
- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -End Footnotes- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -
I am unable to agree that the benefits that may accrue to society from the
compulsory flag salute are sufficiently definite and tangible to justify the
invasion of freedom and privacy that is entailed or to compensate for a
restraint on the freedom of the individual to be vocal or silent according to
his conscience or personal inclination. The trenchant words in the preamble to
the Virginia [***36] Statute for Religious Freedom remain
unanswerable: ". . . all attempts to influence [the mind] by temporal
punishments, or burdens, or by civil incapacitations, tend only to beget habits
of hypocrisy and meanness, . . ." Any spark of love for country which may
be generated in a child or his associates by forcing him to make what is to him
an empty gesture and recite words wrung from him contrary to his religious
beliefs is overshadowed by the desirability of preserving freedom of conscience
to the full. It is in that freedom and the example of persuasion, not in force
and compulsion, that the real unity of America lies.
DISSENTBY: FRANKFURTER
DISSENT: MR. JUSTICE FRANKFURTER, dissenting:
One who belongs to the most vilified and persecuted minority in history is not
likely to be insensible to the freedoms guaranteed by our Constitution. Were my
purely personal attitude relevant I should wholeheartedly associate myself with
the general libertarian views in the Court's opinion, representing as they do
the thought and [*647] action of a lifetime. But as judges we are
neither Jew nor Gentile, neither Catholic nor agnostic. We owe equal attachment
to the Constitution and are equally bound by our judicial [***37]
obligations whether we derive our citizenship from the earliest or the latest
immigrants to these shores. As a member of this Court I am not justified in
writing my private notions of policy into the Constitution, no matter how
deeply I may cherish them or how mischievous I may deem their disregard. The
duty of a judge who must decide which of two claims before the Court shall
prevail, that of a State to enact and enforce laws within its general
competence or that of an individual to refuse obedience because of the demands
of his conscience, is not that of the ordinary person. It can never be
emphasized too much that one's own opinion about the wisdom or evil of a law
should be excluded altogether when one is doing one's duty on the bench. The
only opinion of our own even looking in that direction that is material is our
opinion whether legislators could in reason have enacted such a law. In the
light of all the circumstances, including the history of this question in this
Court, it would require more daring than I possess to deny that reasonable
legislators could have taken the action which is before us for review. Most
unwillingly, therefore, I must differ from my brethren [***38] with
regard to legislation like this. I cannot bring my mind to believe that the
"liberty" secured by the Due Process Clause gives this Court
authority to deny to the State of West Virginia the attainment of that which we
all recognize as a legitimate legislative end, [**1190] namely, the
promotion of good citizenship, by employment of the means here chosen.
Not so long ago we were admonished that "the only check upon our own
exercise of power is our own sense of self-restraint. For the removal of unwise
laws from the statute books appeal lies not to the courts but to the ballot and
to the processes of democratic government." [*648] United
States v. Butler, 297 U.S. 1, 79 (dissent). We have been told
that generalities do not decide concrete cases. But the intensity with which a
general principle is held may determine a particular issue, and whether we put
first things first may decide a specific controversy.
The admonition that judicial self-restraint alone limits arbitrary exercise of
our authority is relevant every time we are asked to nullify legislation. The
Constitution does not give us greater veto power when dealing with one phase of
"liberty" than with another, or [***39] when dealing with
grade school regulations than with college regulations that offend conscience,
as was the case in Hamilton v. Regents, 293 U.S. 245. In
neither situation is our function comparable to that of a legislature or are we
free to act as though we were a super-legislature. Judicial self-restraint is
equally necessary whenever an exercise of political or legislative power is
challenged. There is no warrant in the constitutional basis of this Court's
authority for attributing different roles to it depending upon the nature of
the challenge to the legislation. Our power does not vary according to the
particular provision of the Bill of Rights which is invoked. The right not to
have property taken without just compensation has, so far as the scope of judicial
power is concerned, the same constitutional dignity as the right to be
protected against unreasonable searches and seizures, and the latter has no
less claim than freedom of the press or freedom of speech or religious freedom.
In no instance is this Court the primary protector of the particular liberty
that is invoked. This Court has recognized, what hardly could be denied, that
all the provisions of the [***40] first ten Amendments are
"specific" prohibitions, United States v. Carolene
Products Co., 304 U.S. 144, 152, n. 4. But each specific Amendment, in so
far as embraced within the Fourteenth Amendment, must be equally respected, and
the function of this [*649] Court does not differ in passing on the
constitutionality of legislation challenged under different Amendments.
When Mr. Justice Holmes, speaking for this Court, wrote that "it must be
remembered that legislatures are ultimate guardians of the liberties and
welfare of the people in quite as great a degree as the courts," Missouri,
K. & T. Ry. Co. v. May, 194 U.S. 267, 270, he went to the
very essence of our constitutional system and the democratic conception of our
society. He did not mean that for only some phases of civil government this
Court was not to supplant legislatures and sit in judgment upon the right or
wrong of a challenged measure. He was stating the comprehensive judicial duty
and role of this Court in our constitutional scheme whenever legislation is
sought to be nullified on any ground, namely, that responsibility for legislation
lies with legislatures, answerable as they are directly to [***41]
the people, and this Court's only and very narrow function is to determine
whether within the broad grant of authority vested in legislatures they have
exercised a judgment for which reasonable justification can be offered.
The framers of the federal Constitution might have chosen to assign an active
share in the process of legislation to this Court. They had before them the
well-known example of New York's Council of Revision, which had been
functioning since 1777. After stating that "laws inconsistent with the
spirit of this constitution, or with the public good, may be hastily and
unadvisedly passed," the state constitution made the judges of New York
part of the legislative process by providing that "all bills which have
passed the senate and assembly shall, before they become laws," be
presented to a Council of which the judges constituted a majority, "for
their revisal and consideration." Art. III, New York Constitution of 1777.
Judges exercised this legislative function in New York [*650] for
nearly fifty years. See Art. I, § 12, New York Constitution of 1821. But the
framers of the Constitution denied such legislative powers to the federal
judiciary. [**1191] They chose [***42] instead to
insulate the judiciary from the legislative function. They did not grant to
this Court supervision over legislation.
The reason why from the beginning even the narrow judicial authority to nullify
legislation has been viewed with a jealous eye is that it serves to prevent the
full play of the democratic process. The fact that it may be an undemocratic
aspect of our scheme of government does not call for its rejection or its
disuse. But it is the best of reasons, as this Court has frequently recognized,
for the greatest caution in its use.
The precise scope of the question before us defines the limits of the
constitutional power that is in issue. The State of West Virginia requires all
pupils to share in the salute to the flag as part of school training in
citizenship. The present action is one to enjoin the enforcement of this
requirement by those in school attendance. We have not before us any attempt by
the State to punish disobedient children or visit penal consequences on their parents.
All that is in question is the right of the State to compel participation in
this exercise by those who choose to attend the public schools.
We are not reviewing merely the [***43] action of a local school
board. The flag salute requirement in this case comes before us with the full
authority of the State of West Virginia. We are in fact passing judgment on
"the power of the State as a whole." Rippey v. Texas,
193 U.S. 504, 509; Skiriotes v. Florida, 313 U.S. 69, 79.
Practically we are passing upon the political power of each of the forty-eight
states. Moreover, since the First Amendment has been read into the Fourteenth,
our problem is precisely the same as it would be if we had before us an Act of
Congress for the District of Columbia. To suggest that we are here concerned
[*651] with the heedless action of some village tyrants is to
distort the augustness of the constitutional issue and the reach of the
consequences of our decision.
Under our constitutional system the legislature is charged solely with civil
concerns of society. If the avowed or intrinsic legislative purpose is either
to promote or to discourage some religious community or creed, it is clearly
within the constitutional restrictions imposed on legislatures and cannot stand.
But it by no means follows that legislative power is wanting whenever a general
non-discriminatory [***44] civil regulation in fact touches
conscientious scruples or religious beliefs of an individual or a group. Regard
for such scruples or beliefs undoubtedly presents one of the most reasonable
claims for the exertion of legislative accommodation. It is, of course, beyond
our power to rewrite the State's requirement, by providing exemptions for those
who do not wish to participate in the flag salute or by making some other
accommodations to meet their scruples. That wisdom might suggest the making of
such accommodations and that school administration would not find it too
difficult to make them and yet maintain the ceremony for those not refusing to
conform, is outside our province to suggest. Tact, respect, and generosity
toward variant views will always commend themselves to those charged with the
duties of legislation so as to achieve a maximum of good will and to require a
minimum of unwilling submission to a general law. But the real question is, who
is to make such accommodations, the courts or the legislature?
This is no dry, technical matter. It cuts deep into one's conception of the
democratic process -- it concerns no less the practical differences between the
means for [***45] making these accommodations that are open to
courts and to legislatures. A court can only strike down. It can only say
"This or that law is void." It cannot modify or qualify, it cannot
make exceptions to a general requirement. [*652] And it strikes
down not merely for a day. At least the finding of unconstitutionality ought
not to have ephemeral significance unless the Constitution is to be reduced to
the fugitive importance of mere legislation. When we are dealing with the
Constitution of the United States, and more particularly with the great
safeguards of the Bill of Rights, we are dealing with principles of liberty and
justice "so rooted in the traditions and conscience of our people as to be
ranked as fundamental" -- something without which " a fair and
enlightened system of justice would be impossible." Palko v. Connecticut,
302 U.S. 319, 325; Hurtado v. California, 110 U.S. 516, 530,
531. [**1192] If the function of this Court is to be essentially no
different from that of a legislature, if the considerations governing
constitutional construction are to be substantially those that underlie
legislation, then indeed judges should not have life tenure and they should
[***46] be made directly responsible to the electorate. There have
been many but unsuccessful proposals in the last sixty years to amend the
Constitution to that end. See Sen. Doc. No. 91, 75th Cong., 1st Sess., pp.
248-51.
Conscientious scruples, all would admit, cannot stand against every legislative
compulsion to do positive acts in conflict with such scruples. We have been
told that such compulsions override religious scruples only as to major
concerns of the state. But the determination of what is major and what is minor
itself raises questions of policy. For the way in which men equally guided by
reason appraise importance goes to the very heart of policy. Judges should be
very diffident in setting their judgment against that of a state in determining
what is and what is not a major concern, what means are appropriate to proper
ends, and what is the total social cost in striking the balance of
imponderables.
What one can say with assurance is that the history out of which grew
constitutional provisions for religious equality [*653] and the writings
of the great exponents of religious freedom -- Jefferson, Madison, John Adams,
Benjamin Franklin -- are totally wanting in [***47] justification
for a claim by dissidents of exceptional immunity from civic measures of
general applicability, measures not in fact disguised assaults upon such
dissident views. The great leaders of the American Revolution were determined
to remove political support from every religious establishment. They put on an
equality the different religious sects -- Episcopalians, Presbyterians,
Catholics, Baptists, Methodists, Quakers, Huguenots -- which, as dissenters,
had been under the heel of the various orthodoxies that prevailed in different
colonies. So far as the state was concerned, there was to be neither orthodoxy
nor heterodoxy. And so Jefferson and those who followed him wrote guaranties of
religious freedom into our constitutions. Religious minorities as well as
religious majorities were to be equal in the eyes of the political state. But
Jefferson and the others also knew that minorities may disrupt society. It
never would have occurred to them to write into the Constitution the
subordination of the general civil authority of the state to sectarian
scruples.
The constitutional protection of religious freedom terminated disabilities, it
did not create new privileges. [***48] It gave religious equality,
not civil immunity. Its essence is freedom from conformity to religious dogma,
not freedom from conformity to law because of religious dogma. Religious loyalties
may be exercised without hindrance from the state, not the state may not
exercise that which except by leave of religious loyalties is within the domain
of temporal power. Otherwise each individual could set up his own censor
against obedience to laws conscientiously deemed for the public good by those
whose business it is to make laws.
The prohibition against any religious establishment by the government placed
denominations on an equal footing -- it [*654] assured freedom from
support by the government to any mode of worship and the freedom of individuals
to support any mode of worship. Any person may therefore believe or disbelieve
what he pleases. He may practice what he will in his own house of worship or
publicly within the limits of public order. But the lawmaking authority is not
circumscribed by the variety of religious beliefs, otherwise the constitutional
guaranty would be not a protection of the free exercise of religion but a
denial of the exercise of legislation.
The [***49] essence of the religious freedom guaranteed by our
Constitution is therefore this: no religion shall either receive the state's
support or incur its hostility. Religion is outside the sphere of political
government. This does not mean that all matters on which religious organizations
or beliefs may pronounce are outside the sphere of government. Were this so,
instead of the separation of church and state, there would be the subordination
of the state on any matter deemed within the sovereignty of the religious
conscience. Much that is the concern of temporal authority affects the
spiritual interests of men. But it is not enough to strike down a
non-discriminatory [**1193] law that it may hurt or offend some
dissident view. It would be too easy to cite numerous prohibitions and
injunctions to which laws run counter if the variant interpretations of the
Bible were made the tests of obedience to law. The validity of secular laws
cannot be measured by their conformity to religious doctrines. It is only in a
theocratic state that ecclesiastical doctrines measure legal right or wrong.
An act compelling profession of allegiance to a religion, no matter how subtly
or tenuously promoted, is [***50] bad. But an act promoting good
citizenship and national allegiance is within the domain of governmental
authority and is therefore to be judged by the same considerations of power and
of constitutionality as those involved in the many [*655] claims of
immunity from civil obedience because of religious scruples.
That claims are pressed on behalf of sincere religious convictions does not of
itself establish their constitutional validity. Nor does waving the banner of
religious freedom relieve us from examining into the power we are asked to deny
the states. Otherwise the doctrine of separation of church and state, so
cardinal in the history of this nation and for the liberty of our people, would
mean not the disestablishment of a state church but the establishment of all
churches and of all religious groups.
The subjection of dissidents to the general requirement of saluting the flag,
as a measure conducive to the training of children in good citizenship, is very
far from being the first instance of exacting obedience to general laws that
have offended deep religious scruples. Compulsory vaccination, see Jacobson
v. Massachusetts, 197 U.S. 11, food inspection regulations,
[***51] see Shapiro v. Lyle, 30 F.2d 971, the
obligation to bear arms, see Hamilton v. Regents, 293 U.S.
245, 267, testimonial duties, see Stansbury v. Marks, 2 Dall.
213, compulsory medical treatment, see People v. Vogelgesang,
221 N. Y. 290, 116 N. E. 977 -- these are but illustrations of conduct that has
often been compelled in the enforcement of legislation of general applicability
even though the religious consciences of particular individuals rebelled at the
exaction.
Law is concerned with external behavior and not with the inner life of man. It
rests in large measure upon compulsion. Socrates lives in history partly
because he gave his life for the conviction that duty of obedience to secular
law does not presuppose consent to its enactment or belief in its virtue. The
consent upon which free government rests is the consent that comes from sharing
in the process of making and unmaking laws. The state is not shut out from a
domain because the individual conscience may deny the state's claim. The
individual conscience [*656] may profess what faith it chooses. It
may affirm and promote that faith -- in the language of the Constitution, it
may [***52] "exercise" it freely -- but it cannot thereby
restrict community action through political organs in matters of community
concern, so long as the action is not asserted in a discriminatory way either
openly or by stealth. One may have the right to practice one's religion and at
the same time owe the duty of formal obedience to laws that run counter to
one's beliefs. Compelling belief implies denial of opportunity to combat it and
to assert dissident views. Such compulsion is one thing. Quite another matter
is submission to conformity of action while denying its wisdom or virtue and
with ample opportunity for seeking its change or abrogation.
In Hamilton v. Regents, 293 U.S. 245, this Court unanimously held
that one attending a state-maintained university cannot refuse attendance on
courses that offend his religious scruples. That decision is not overruled
today, but is distinguished on the ground that attendance at the institution
for higher education was voluntary and therefore a student could not refuse
compliance with its conditions and yet take advantage of its opportunities. But
West Virginia does not compel the attendance at its public schools of the
children here [***53] concerned. West Virginia does not so compel,
for it cannot. This Court denied the right of a state to require its children
to attend public schools. Pierce v. Society of Sisters, 268
U.S. 510. As to its public schools, West Virginia imposes conditions
[**1194] which it deems necessary in the development of future
citizens precisely as California deemed necessary the requirements that
offended the student's conscience in the Hamilton case. The need for
higher education and the duty of the state to provide it as part of a public educational
system, are part of the democratic faith of most of our states. The right to
secure such education in institutions not maintained by public funds is
unquestioned. [*657] But the practical opportunities for obtaining
what is becoming in increasing measure the conventional equipment of American
youth may be no less burdensome than that which parents are increasingly called
upon to bear in sending their children to parochial schools because the
education provided by public schools, though supported by their taxes, does not
satisfy their ethical and educational necessities. I find it impossible, so far
as constitutional power is concerned, [***54] to differentiate what
was sanctioned in the Hamilton case from what is nullified in this
case. And for me it still remains to be explained why the grounds of Mr.
Justice Cardozo's opinion in Hamilton v. Regents, supra, are
not sufficient to sustain the flag salute requirement. Such a requirement, like
the requirement in the Hamilton case, "is not an interference by
the state with the free exercise of religion when the liberties of the
constitution are read in the light of a century and a half of history during
days of peace and war." 293 U.S. 245, 266. The religious worshiper,
"if his liberties were to be thus extended, might refuse to contribute
taxes . . . in furtherance of any other end condemned by his conscience as
irreligious or immoral. The right of private judgment has never yet been so
exalted above the powers and the compulsion of the agencies of government."
Id., at 268.
Parents have the privilege of choosing which schools they wish their children
to attend. And the question here is whether the state may make certain
requirements that seem to it desirable or important for the proper education of
those future citizens who go to schools maintained [***55] by the
states, or whether the pupils in those schools may be relieved from those
requirements if they run counter to the consciences of their parents. Not only
have parents the right to send children to schools of their own choosing but
the state has no right to bring such schools "under a strict governmental
control" or give "affirmative direction [*658] concerning
the intimate and essential details of such schools, entrust their control to public
officers, and deny both owners and patrons reasonable choice and discretion in
respect of teachers, curriculum, and textbooks." Farrington v. Tokushige,
273 U.S. 284, 298. Why should not the state likewise have constitutional power
to make reasonable provisions for the proper instruction of children in schools
maintained by it?
When dealing with religious scruples we are dealing with an almost numberless
variety of doctrines and beliefs entertained with equal sincerity by the
particular groups for which they satisfy man's needs in his relation to the
mysteries of the universe. There are in the United States more than 250
distinctive established religious denominations. In the State of Pennsylvania
there are 120 of these, [***56] and in West Virginia as many as 65.
But if religious scruples afford immunity from civic obedience to laws, they
may be invoked by the religious beliefs of any individual even though he holds
no membership in any sect or organized denomination. Certainly this Court
cannot be called upon to determine what claims of conscience should be
recognized and what should be rejected as satisfying the "religion"
which the Constitution protects. That would indeed resurrect the very
discriminatory treatment of religion which the Constitution sought forever to
forbid. And so, when confronted with the task of considering the claims of
immunity from obedience to a law dealing with civil affairs because of
religious scruples, we cannot conceive religion more narrowly than in the terms
in which Judge Augustus N. Hand recently characterized it:
"It is unnecessary to attempt a definition of religion; the content of the
term is found in the history of the human race and is incapable of compression
into a few words. Religious belief arises from a sense of the inadequacy of
reason [*659] as a means of relating the individual to his
fellowmen [**1195] and to his universe. . . . [It] may justly be
regarded [***57] as a response of the individual to an inward
mentor, call it conscience or God, that is for many persons at the present time
the equivalent of what has always been thought a religious impulse." United
States v. Kauten, 133 F.2d 703, 708.
Consider the controversial issue of compulsory Bible-reading in public schools.
The educational policies of the states are in great conflict over this, and the
state courts are divided in their decisions on the issue whether the
requirement of Bible-reading offends constitutional provisions dealing with
religious freedom. The requirement of Bible-reading has been justified by
various state courts as an appropriate means of inculcating ethical precepts
and familiarizing pupils with the most lasting expression of great English
literature. Is this Court to overthrow such variant state educational policies
by denying states the right to entertain such convictions in regard to their
school systems, because of a belief that the King James version is in fact a
sectarian text to which parents of the Catholic and Jewish faiths and of some
Protestant persuasions may rightly object to having their children exposed? On
the other hand the religious [***58] consciences of some parents
may rebel at the absence of any Bible-reading in the schools. See Washington
ex rel. Clithero v. Showalter, 284 U.S. 573. Or is this Court to
enter the old controversy between science and religion by unduly defining the
limits within which a state may experiment with its school curricula? The
religious consciences of some parents may be offended by subjecting their
children to the Biblical account of creation, while another state may offend
parents by prohibiting a teaching of biology that contradicts such Biblical
account. Compare Scopes v. State, 154 Tenn. 105, 289 S. W.
363. What of conscientious [*660] objections to what is devoutly felt
by parents to be the poisoning of impressionable minds of children by
chauvinistic teaching of history? This is very far from a fanciful suggestion
for in the belief of many thoughtful people nationalism is the seed-bed of war.
There are other issues in the offing which admonish us of the difficulties and
complexities that confront states in the duty of administering their local
school systems. All citizens are taxed for the support of public schools
although this Court has denied the right [***59] of a state to
compel all children to go to such schools and has recognized the right of
parents to send children to privately maintained schools. Parents who are
dissatisfied with the public schools thus carry a double educational burden.
Children who go to public school enjoy in many states derivative advantages
such as free textbooks, free lunch, and free transportation in going to and
from school. What of the claims for equality of treatment of those parents who,
because of religious scruples, cannot send their children to public schools?
What of the claim that if the right to send children to privately maintained
schools is partly an exercise of religious conviction, to render effective this
right it should be accompanied by equality of treatment by the state in
supplying free textbooks, free lunch, and free transportation to children who
go to private schools? What of the claim that such grants are offensive to the
cardinal constitutional doctrine of separation of church and state?
These questions assume increasing importance in view of the steady growth of
parochical schools both in number and in population. I am not borrowing trouble
by adumbrating these issues nor [***60] am I parading horrible
examples of the consequences of today's decision. I am aware that we must
decide the case before us and not some other case. But that does not mean that
a case is dissociated from the past and unrelated to the future. We must decide
this [*661] case with due regard for what went before and no less
regard for what may come after. Is it really a fair construction of such a
fundamental concept as the right freely to exercise one's religion that a state
cannot choose to require all children who attend public school to make the same
gesture of allegiance to the symbol of our national life because it may offend
the conscience of some children, but that it may compel all children to attend
public school to listen to the King James version although it may offend the
consciences of their parents? And what of the larger issue of claiming immunity
from obedience to a general civil regulation that has a reasonable
[**1196] relation to a public purpose within the general competence
of the state? See Pierce v. Society of Sisters, 268 U.S. 510,
535. Another member of the sect now before us insisted that in forbidding her
two little girls, aged nine and twelve, to distribute [***61]
pamphlets Oregon infringed her and their freedom of religion in that the
children were engaged in "preaching the gospel of God's Kingdom." A procedural
technicality led to the dismissal of the case, but the problem remains. McSparran
v. Portland, 318 U.S. 768.
These questions are not lightly stirred. They touch the most delicate issues
and their solution challenges the best wisdom of political and religious
statesmen. But it presents awful possibilities to try to encase the solution of
these problems within the rigid prohibitions of unconstitutionality.
We are told that a flag salute is a doubtful substitute for adequate
understanding of our institutions. The states that require such a school
exercise do not have to justify it as the only means for promoting good
citizenship in children, but merely as one of diverse means for accomplishing a
worthy end. We may deem it a foolish measure, but the point is that this Court
is not the organ of government to resolve doubts as to whether it will fulfill
its purpose. Only if there be no doubt that any reasonable [*662]
mind could entertain can we deny to the states the right to resolve doubts
their way and not ours.
That [***62] which to the majority may seem essential for the
welfare of the state may offend the consciences of a minority. But, so long as
no inroads are made upon the actual exercise of religion by the minority, to
deny the political power of the majority to enact laws concerned with civil
matters, simply because they may offend the consciences of a minority, really
means that the consciences of a minority are more sacred and more enshrined in
the Constitution than the consciences of a majority.
We are told that symbolism is a dramatic but primitive way of communicating
ideas. Symbolism is inescapable. Even the most sophisticated live by symbols.
But it is not for this Court to make psychological judgments as to the
effectiveness of a particular symbol in inculcating concededly indispensable
feelings, particularly if the state happens to see fit to utilize the symbol
that represents our heritage and our hopes. And surely only flippancy could be
responsible for the suggestion that constitutional validity of a requirement to
salute our flag implies equal validity of a requirement to salute a dictator.
The significance of a symbol lies in what it represents. To reject the swastika
does [***63] not imply rejection of the Cross. And so it bears
repetition to say that it mocks reason and denies our whole history to find in
the allowance of a requirement to salute our flag on fitting occasions the
seeds of sanction for obeisance to a leader. To deny the power to employ
educational symbols is to say that the state's educational system may not
stimulate the imagination because this may lead to unwise stimulation.
The right of West Virginia to utilize the flag salute as part of its
educational process is denied because, so it is argued, it cannot be justified
as a means of meeting a "clear and present danger" to national unity.
In passing it deserves to be noted that the four cases which unanimously
[*663] sustained the power of states to utilize such an educational
measure arose and were all decided before the present World War. But to measure
the state's power to make such regulations as are here resisted by the
imminence of national danger is wholly to misconceive the origin and purpose of
the concept of "clear and present danger." To apply such a test is
for the Court to assume, however unwittingly, a legislative responsibility that
does not belong to it. To talk [***64] about "clear and
present danger" as the touchstone of allowable educational policy by the
states whenever school curricula may impinge upon the boundaries of individual
conscience, is to take a felicitous phrase out of the context of the particular
situation where it arose and for which it was adapted. Mr. Justice Holmes used
the phrase "clear and present danger" in a case involving mere speech
as a means by which alone to accomplish sedition in time of war. By that phrase
he meant merely to indicate that, in view of the protection given to utterance
by the First Amendment, in order that mere utterance may [**1197]
not be proscribed, "the words used are used in such circumstances and are
of such a nature as to create a clear and present danger that they will bring
about the substantive evils that Congress has a right to prevent." Schenck
v. United States, 249 U.S. 47, 52. The "substantive evils"
about which he was speaking were inducement of insubordination in the military
and naval forces of the United States and obstruction of enlistment while the
country was at war. He was not enunciating a formal rule that there can be no
restriction upon speech and, still less, no compulsion [***65]
where conscience balks, unless imminent danger would thereby be wrought
"to our institutions or our government."
The flag salute exercise has no kinship whatever to the oath tests so odious in
history. For the oath test was one of the instruments for suppressing heretical
beliefs. [*664] Saluting the flag suppresses no belief nor curbs
it. Children and their parents may believe what they please, avow their belief
and practice it. It is not even remotely suggested that the requirement for
saluting the flag involves the slightest restriction against the fullest
opportunity on the part both of the children and of their parents to disavow as
publicly as they choose to do so the meaning that others attach to the gesture
of salute. All channels of affirmative free expression are open to both
children and parents. Had we before us any act of the state putting the
slightest curbs upon such free expression, I should not lag behind any member of
this Court in striking down such an invasion of the right to freedom of thought
and freedom of speech protected by the Constitution.
I am fortified in my view of this case by the history of the flag salute
controversy in this Court. Five [***66] times has the precise
question now before us been adjudicated. Four times the Court unanimously found
that the requirement of such a school exercise was not beyond the powers of the
states. Indeed in the first three cases to come before the Court the constitutional
claim now sustained was deemed so clearly unmeritorious that this Court
dismissed the appeals for want of a substantial federal question. Leoles
v. Landers, 302 U.S. 656; Hering v. State Board of
Education, 303 U.S. 624; Gabrielli v. Knickerbocker, 306
U.S. 621. In the fourth case the judgment of the district court upholding the
state law was summarily affirmed on the authority of the earlier cases. Johnson
v. Deerfield, 306 U.S. 621. The fifth case, Minersville District
v. Gobitis, 310 U.S. 586, was brought here because the decision of the
Circuit Court of Appeals for the Third Circuit ran counter to our rulings. They
were reaffirmed after full consideration, with one Justice dissenting.
What may be even more significant than this uniform recognition of state
authority is the fact that every Justice -- thirteen [*665] in all
-- who has hitherto participated in judging [***67] this matter has
at one or more times found no constitutional infirmity in what is now
condemned. Only the two Justices sitting for the first time on this matter have
not heretofore found this legislation inoffensive to the "liberty"
guaranteed by the Constitution. And among the Justices who sustained this
measure were outstanding judicial leaders in the zealous enforcement of constitutional
safeguards of civil liberties -- men like Chief Justice Hughes, Mr. Justice
Brandeis, and Mr. Justice Cardozo, to mention only those no longer on the
Court.
One's conception of the Constitution cannot be severed from one's conception of
a judge's function in applying it. The Court has no reason for existence if it
merely reflects the pressures of the day. Our system is built on the faith that
men set apart for this special function, freed from the influences of immediacy
and from the deflections of worldly ambition, will become able to take a view
of longer range than the period of responsibility entrusted to Congress and
legislatures. We are dealing with matters as to which legislators and voters
have conflicting views. Are we as judges to impose our strong convictions on
where wisdom [***68] lies? That which three years ago had seemed to
five successive Courts to lie within permissible areas of legislation is now
outlawed by the deciding shift of opinion of two Justices. What reason is there
to believe that they or their successors may not have another view a few years
hence? Is that which was [**1198] deemed to be of so fundamental a
nature as to be written into the Constitution to endure for all times to be the
sport of shifting winds of doctrine? Of course, judicial opinions, even as to
questions of constitutionality, are not immutable. As has been true in the
past, the Court will from time to time reverse its position. But I believe that
never before these Jehovah's Witnesses [*666] cases (except for
minor deviations subsequently retraced) has this Court overruled decisions so
as to restrict the powers of democratic government. Always heretofore, it has
withdrawn narrow views of legislative authority so as to authorize what
formerly it had denied.
In view of this history it must be plain that what thirteen Justices found to
be within the constitutional authority of a state, legislators can not be
deemed unreasonable in enacting. Therefore, in denying to the states
[***69] what heretofore has received such impressive judicial
sanction, some other tests of unconstitutionality must surely be guiding the
Court than the absence of a rational justification for the legislation. But I
know of no other test which this Court is authorized to apply in nullifying
legislation.
In the past this Court has from time to time set its views of policy against
that embodied in legislation by finding laws in conflict with what was called
the "spirit of the Constitution." Such undefined destructive power
was not conferred on this Court by the Constitution. Before a duly enacted law
can be judicially nullified, it must be forbidden by some explicit restriction
upon political authority in the Constitution. Equally inadmissible is the claim
to strike down legislation because to us as individuals it seems opposed to the
"plan and purpose" of the Constitution. That is too tempting a basis
for finding in one's personal views the purposes of the Founders.
The uncontrollable power wielded by this Court brings it very close to the most
sensitive areas of public affairs. As appeal from legislation to adjudication
becomes more frequent, and its consequences more far-reaching,
[***70] judicial self-restraint becomes more and not less
important, lest we unwarrantably enter social and political domains wholly
outside our concern. I think I appreciate fully the objections to the law
before us. But to deny that it presents a question upon which men might
reasonably [*667] differ appears to me to be intolerance. And since
men may so reasonably differ, I deem it beyond my constitutional power to
assert my view of the wisdom of this law against the view of the State of West
Virginia.
Jefferson's opposition to judicial review has not been accepted by history, but
it still serves as an admonition against confusion between judicial and
political functions. As a rule of judicial self-restraint, it is still as valid
as Lincoln's admonition. For those who pass laws not only are under duty to
pass laws. They are also under duty to observe the Constitution. And even
though legislation relates to civil liberties, our duty of deference to those
who have the responsibility for making the laws is no less relevant or less
exacting. And this is so especially when we consider the accidental
contingencies by which one man may determine constitutionality and thereby
confine [***71] the political power of the Congress of the United
States and the legislatures of forty-eight states. The attitude of judicial
humility which these considerations enjoin is not an abdication of the judicial
function. It is a due observance of its limits. Moreover, it is to be borne in
mind that in a question like this we are not passing on the proper distribution
of political power as between the states and the central government. We are not
discharging the basic function of this Court as the mediator of powers within
the federal system. To strike down a law like this is to deny a power to all
government.
The whole Court is conscious that this case reaches ultimate questions of
judicial power and its relation to our scheme of government. It is appropriate,
therefore, to recall an utterance as wise as any that I know in analyzing what
is really involved when the theory of this Court's function is put to the test of
practice. The analysis is that of James Bradley Thayer:
". . . there has developed a vast and growing increase of judicial
interference with legislation. This is a very different [*668]
state of things from what our fathers contemplated, a century and more ago,
[***72] in framing the new system. Seldom, indeed, as they
imagined, under our system, [**1199] would this great, novel,
tremendous power of the courts be exerted, -- would this sacred ark of the
covenant be taken from within the veil. Marshall himself expressed truly one
aspect of the matter, when he said in one of the later years of his life: 'No
questions can be brought before a judicial tribunal of greater delicacy than
those which involve the constitutionality of legislative acts. If they become
indispensably necessary to the case, the court must meet and decide them; but
if the case may be determined on other grounds, a just respect for the
legislature requires that the obligation of its laws should not be
unnecessarily and wantonly assailed.' And again, a little earlier than this, he
laid down the one true rule of duty for the courts. When he went to
Philadelphia at the end of September, in 1831, on that painful errand of which
I have spoken, in answering a cordial tribute from the bar of that city he
remarked that if he might be permitted to claim for himself and his associates
any part of the kind things they had said, it would be this, that they had
'never sought to enlarge the judicial [***73] power beyond its
proper bounds, nor feared to carry it to the fullest extent that duty
required.'
"That is the safe twofold rule; nor is the first part of it any whit less
important than the second; nay, more; today it is the part which most requires
to be emphasized. For just here comes in a consideration of very great weight.
Great and, indeed, inestimable as are the advantages in a popular government of
this conservative influence, -- the power of the judiciary to disregard
unconstitutional legislation, -- it should be remembered that the exercise of
it, even when unavoidable, is always attended with a serious evil, namely, that
the correction of legislative mistakes comes from the outside, and the people
thus lose the political experience, and the moral education and stimulus that
come from fighting the question out in the ordinary way, and correcting their
own errors. If the decision in Munn v. Illinois and the 'Granger
Cases,' twenty-five years ago, and in the 'Legal Tender Cases,' nearly thirty
years [*669] ago, had been different; and the legislation there in
question, thought by many to be unconstitutional and by many more to be
ill-advised, had been set aside, [***74] we should have been saved
some trouble and some harm. But I venture to think that the good which came to
the country and its people from the vigorous thinking that had to be done in
the political debates that followed, from the infiltration through every part
of the population of sound ideas and sentiments, from the rousing into activity
of opposite elements, the enlargement of ideas, the strengthening of moral
fibre, and the growth of political experience that came out of it all, -- that
all this far more than outweighed any evil which ever flowed from the refusal
of the court to interfere with the work of the legislature.
"The tendency of a common and easy resort to this great function, now
lamentably too common, is to dwarf the political capacity of the people, and to
deaden its sense of moral responsibility. It is no light thing to do that.
"What can be done? It is the courts that can do most to cure the evil; and
the opportunity is a very great one. Let them resolutely adhere to first
principles. Let them consider how narrow is the function which the
constitutions have conferred on them -- the office merely of deciding litigated
cases; how large, therefore, is the duty [***75] intrusted to
others, and above all to the legislature. It is that body which is charged,
primarily, with the duty of judging of the constitutionality of its work. The
constitutions generally give them no authority to call upon a court for advice;
they must decide for themselves, and the courts may never be able to say a
word. Such a body, charged, in every State, with almost all the legislative
power of the people, is entitled to the most entire and real respect; is
entitled, as among all rationally permissible opinions as to what the
constitution allows, to its own choice. Courts, as has often been said, are not
to think of the legislators, but of the legislature -- the great, continuous
body itself, abstracted from all the transitory individuals who may happen to
hold its power. It is this majestic representative of the people whose action
is in question, a coordinate department of the government, [*670]
charged with the greatest functions, and invested, in contemplation of law,
with whatsoever wisdom, virtue, and knowledge the exercise of such functions
requires.
" [**1200] To set aside the acts of such a body, representing
in its own field, which is the very highest of all, the [***76]
ultimate sovereign, should be a solemn, unusual, and painful act. Something is
wrong when it can ever be other than that. And if it be true that the holders
of legislative power are careless or evil, yet the constitutional duty of the
court remains untouched; it cannot rightly attempt to protect the people, by
undertaking a function not its own. On the other hand, by adhering rigidly to
its own duty, the court will help, as nothing else can, to fix the spot where
responsibility lies, and to bring down on that precise locality the thunderbolt
of popular condemnation. The judiciary, today, in dealing with the acts of
their coordinate legislators, owe to the country no greater or clearer duty
than that of keeping their hands off these acts wherever it is possible to do
it. For that course -- the true course of judicial duty always -- will
powerfully help to bring the people and their representatives to a sense of
their own responsibility. There will still remain to the judiciary an ample
field for the determinations of this remarkable jurisdiction, of which our
American law has so much reason to be proud; a jurisdiction which has had some
of its chief illustrations and its greatest [***77] triumphs, as in
Marshall's time, so in ours, while the courts were refusing to exercise
it." J. B. Thayer, John Marshall, (1901) 104-10.
Of course patriotism can not be enforced by the flag salute. But neither can
the liberal spirit be enforced by judicial invalidation of illiberal
legislation. Our constant preoccupation with the constitutionality of
legislation rather than with its wisdom tends to preoccupation of the American
mind with a false value. The tendency of focussing attention on
constitutionality is to make constitutionality synonymous with wisdom, to regard
a law as all right if it is constitutional. Such an attitude is a great enemy
of liberalism. Particularly in legislation affecting freedom of thought and
freedom of speech much which should offend a free-spirited society is
constitutional. Reliance [*671] for the most precious interests of
civilization, therefore, must be found outside of their vindication in courts
of law. Only a persistent positive translation of the faith of a free society
into the convictions and habits and actions of a community is the ultimate
reliance against unabated temptations to fetter the human spirit.